Besides the ordinary set operations, there are special operations we can perform on relations.
Definition. The inverse of a relation from
to
is the relation from
to
defined by:
That is, iff
iff
iff
.
E.g. iff
iff
.
That is, the inverse of the less-than relation is the greater-than relation.
Note that the inverse and the complement are very different things, because the complement of less-than is greater-than-or-equal-to.
Exercise. What is the inverse of the identity relation?
Definition. If is a relation from
to
and
is a relation from
to
, we define the {\em composite relation}
from
to
by:
Note that the source of is the source of
and the target of
is the target of
.
We can think of as a stepping stone between
and
.
consists of all the pairs
such that there is such a stepping stone, as we pass from the source of
to the target of
.
Observe that unless the target of and the source of
are the same, we can't even make sense of
. So most composites aren't defined, and we must first check that two relations are compatible before we try to compose them. Even if
is defined,
usually isn't.
In lower mathematics courses, you probably only encountered relations on , so that all sources and targets were the same---thus, all compositions were defined. The sole exception to this is in multivariable calculus. This is precisely why the multivariable Chain Rule is so much more complicated than its single-variable counterpart.
Exercise. Formulate the definition of in infix notation. That is, explain what
means.
Exercise. Consider the set of all people, and the relations
and
on
given by:
iff
is
's mother and
iff
is
's father. Explain what the following relations mean:
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
,
.
Theorem. Let be a relation from
to
,
a relation from
to
, and
a relation from
to
. Then
and
and
.
Proof. We'll prove the last clause, and leave the others as exercises.
Since we need to prove , let
. Then
for some
. Since
, there is some
with
. So
. So
.
To show , let
. Then
for some
. Since
, there is some
with
. Then
. So
.